ImageVerifierCode 换一换
格式:DOCX , 页数:7 ,大小:20.81KB ,
资源ID:22771583      下载积分:3 金币
快捷下载
登录下载
邮箱/手机:
温馨提示:
快捷下载时,用户名和密码都是您填写的邮箱或者手机号,方便查询和重复下载(系统自动生成)。 如填写123,账号就是123,密码也是123。
特别说明:
请自助下载,系统不会自动发送文件的哦; 如果您已付费,想二次下载,请登录后访问:我的下载记录
支付方式: 支付宝    微信支付   
验证码:   换一换

加入VIP,免费下载
 

温馨提示:由于个人手机设置不同,如果发现不能下载,请复制以下地址【https://www.bdocx.com/down/22771583.html】到电脑端继续下载(重复下载不扣费)。

已注册用户请登录:
账号:
密码:
验证码:   换一换
  忘记密码?
三方登录: 微信登录   QQ登录  

下载须知

1: 本站所有资源如无特殊说明,都需要本地电脑安装OFFICE2007和PDF阅读器。
2: 试题试卷类文档,如果标题没有明确说明有答案则都视为没有答案,请知晓。
3: 文件的所有权益归上传用户所有。
4. 未经权益所有人同意不得将文件中的内容挪作商业或盈利用途。
5. 本站仅提供交流平台,并不能对任何下载内容负责。
6. 下载文件中如有侵权或不适当内容,请与我们联系,我们立即纠正。
7. 本站不保证下载资源的准确性、安全性和完整性, 同时也不承担用户因使用这些下载资源对自己和他人造成任何形式的伤害或损失。

版权提示 | 免责声明

本文(Uncle Sam Wants You 英语短文文档格式.docx)为本站会员(b****7)主动上传,冰豆网仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。 若此文所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知冰豆网(发送邮件至service@bdocx.com或直接QQ联系客服),我们立即给予删除!

Uncle Sam Wants You 英语短文文档格式.docx

1、DOI: 10.1126/science.284.5417.1131 Books HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCEUncle Sam Wants YouA review by David L. Hull*1. David L. Hull*+ Author Affiliations1. The author is in the Department of Philosophy, Northwestern University, Brentano Hall, 1818 Hinman Avenue, Evanston, IL 60208, USA. E-mail:

2、d-hullnwu.eduMystery of Mysteries Is Evolution a Social Construction? Michael Ruse Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999. 320 pp. $27.50, 16.95. ISBN 0-674-46706-X. Many scientists, possibly most scientists, just do science without thinking too much about it. They run experiments, make obser

3、vations, show how certain data conflict with more general views, set out theories, and so on. Periodically, however, some of usscientists includedstep back and look at what is going on in science. In doing so, students of science use some of the same techniques that scientists use. For example, we a

4、ttempt to show that science is progressive by detailing the history of science over the past couple hundred years. Or we argue that scientists have been strongly influenced by their cultures by looking at particular instances of such cultural influence. In this respect, the study of science is refle

5、xive. We gather data about science to show exactly how influential data are (or are not) in science. The result has been the science wars. The two extreme positions in this dispute over the nature of science are social constructivism and positivism. The most extreme constructivists seem to hold that

6、 all of us, scientists included, are helpless victims in the maws of our societies. We all believe what our societies force us to believe. On this extreme view, the appeals that scientists make to reason, argument, and evidence are merely so much show to cover the social origins of our beliefs. The

7、trouble is that constructivists live in precisely the same societies as the rest of us. Somehow they are able to free themselves from the ineluctable hold that society has on them, but strangely the rest of us cannot. Conversely, positivists are portrayed as evil, insisting that scientific world vie

8、ws are totally devoid of any such considerationsin particular of any appeals to values. Scientists simply tell it like it is. Reason, argument, and evidence are all that matter. Most of the issues that others find so fascinating, including metaphysics, are just nonsense. That positivists spent so mu

9、ch time writing on issues that surely count as metaphysical, including the claim that metaphysics is nonsense, hardly warrants mentioning. As is commonly the case, both sides engaged in the science wars are constantly on the move: advancing, retreating, and covering their tracks, as best as they can

10、, with verbal smoke screens. Combatants on both sides insist that they never held any of the views for which they are famous. Instead, they waffle extensively. Constructivists claim they always acknowledged that reason, argument, and evidence play crucial roles in science. All that they are attempti

11、ng to point out is that social factors also play important roles in science, at times overwhelming more narrowly scientific factors. More traditional philosophers object to being tarred with the same brush as the extreme positivists. Professional and social factors play parts in science, of course,

12、but so do reason, argument, and evidence; and in the long run, more narrowly scientific factors triumph. Hence, the only difference between the two sides is estimation of relative importance. As reasonable as these more moderate positions may seem, their advocates still must confront the problem of

13、reflexivity. How do we decide the relative importance of scientific and cultural factors in the decisions that scientists make? If we study science scientifically, then we run the danger of circularity. If we are to study science in some other ways, what are the outlines of these alternatives? No on

14、e has suggested any yet. It is here that Michael Ruse, in his Mystery of Mysteries, steps into the breach. When John Herschel referred to the mystery of mysteries in 1836, he had in mind the replacement of species through time, what we have come to call biological evolution. Ruse has the evolution o

15、f science in mind, and the evolution of science is as mysterious today as the evolution of species was a century and a half ago. Ruse proposes to investigate the history of evolutionary biology from the late 18th century to the present to determine the influence of various factors in deciding the co

16、urse of this scientific discipline. He selects a dozen or so evolutionary biologists to study. He begins with Erasmus Darwin as a representative of a pre-Darwinian evolutionist. For the 19th century, he quite naturally turns to Erasmus Darwins grandson, Charles, and T. H. Huxley. Then, from this cen

17、tury, Ruse discusses Julian Huxley, Theodosius Dobzhansky, Richard Dawkins, Stephen Jay Gould, Richard Lewontin, E. O. Wilson, Geoffrey Parker, and Jack Sepkoski. Because evolutionary theory has been one of the chief battlefields in the war between constructivists and positivists, Ruse could not hav

18、e picked a more appropriate topic of study. We have all heard, time and again, that the reason Darwins theory was so individualistic, competitive, elitist, sexist, and racist is that Darwins society exhibited these same characteristics. Darwin was so callow that he simply read the characteristics of

19、 his society into nature. Ruse is uniquely prepared to write this book. He has published on the history of evolutionary theory from before Darwin to the present. He is a professional philosopher of science who deals with a wide spectrum of topics, from the role of religion in science to the virtues

20、of formalistic philosophy of science. He also has the courage of his convictionsat the 1982 Arkansas creationism trial he testified that science can be sharply distinguished from non-science, and that evolutionary biology is clearly on the scientific side of the divide while creationism is just as c

21、learly on the unscientific side. As strange as it may sound, courage is required for writing a book such as Mystery of Mysteries. Historians of science usually deal with dead scientists. Dead scientists cannot talk back, nor can they retaliate. Living scientists can. A shiver goes down my spine when

22、 I think of how the living scientists Ruse discusses are likely to respond to his book. But Ruse has always been willing to call em as he sees em. For the past dozen years, he has concluded each issue of his journal Biology & Philosophy with a set of editorial booknotes. As each issue arrives in the

23、 mail, I turn first to his “Booknotes” with equal parts of anticipation and apprehension. What will he say next, and will it be about me?For each of the evolutionary biologists that Ruse studies, he asks how do such traditional epistemic values as predictive ability, consistency, and coherence contr

24、ibute to the biologists work? He also investigates the influence of what he terms “metavalues,” those beliefs that scientists have about science itself. To take one example: in the early days of science, references to God in science were perfectly acceptable, but later such references were excluded.

25、 Finally, Ruse examines whether such cultural factors as beliefs in progress, male dominance, and individualism had significant effects on the path that evolutionary biology has taken. As Ruse works his way from the 18th century to the present, he evaluates each of his subjects, first from a present

26、-day perspective and then according to the standards of the subjects own time. For example, from a present-day perspective, Erasmus Darwins Zoonomia (1794) hardly seems the stuff of scienceafter all, it is a poem. But in his day, his more serious contemporaries also had considerable doubt as to whet

27、her his writings counted as genuine science. Ruse agrees. The influence of epistemic values in the evolutionary writings of Erasmus Darwin was minimal. The effects of other factors were maximal. When Ruse turns to Charles Darwin, the balance shifts dramatically. Darwin tried to make his theory of ev

28、olution look as scientific as possible, with varying degrees of success. One chief difference between the 18th and 19th centuries is that science was well on its way to becoming professionalized in Darwins day, and one of the chief metavalues of professional science was that it had to be as free of

29、nonepistemic values as possible. Regardless of how important a belief in progress may have actually been at the time, scientists had to act as if it did not influence their activities because such beliefs were not genuinely scientific. Darwin joined in this process of constructing science, and here

30、the constructivist notion of “construction” has some bite. Nineteenth-century intellectuals did not simply discover science. To a large extent, they literally constructed it. Darwin, however, was not entirely successful in presenting his theory of evolution as exemplifying the best epistemic and met

31、alevel values of his day. One of the commonest and most effective objections to Darwins theory was that it was not genuine science. Ruse concludes that evolutionary thought in the late 19th century is “more epistemically rigorous than it ever was; yet at all levels it is thoroughly impregnated with

32、culture” (p. 80). As Ruse turns to evolutionary biology in the early 20th century, the difference between the science of then and today diminishes rapidly because the science of the day was rapidly becoming the science of today. The founders of the synthetic, or neo-Darwinian, theory of evolution were concerned to make evolutionary theory even more scientific than it had been, in particular more mathematical. Even so, nonepistemic factors were also operative. Several evolutionists, such as Julian Huxley, wanted to replace Christianity with a secular re

copyright@ 2008-2022 冰豆网网站版权所有

经营许可证编号:鄂ICP备2022015515号-1